1. How is the public image of Epicurus that has come down to us "gravely flawed"?
2. What question expresses the metaphysical problem of The One and the Many? Do you think the senses are more a veil from or a bridge to the real world?
3. Do you agree with Heraclitus or Parmenides? Is it wise or appropriate to "philosophize in poetry"?
4. Do you think empty space truly exists?
5. Should we credit the early Atomists with "speculative depth" or were they just lucky?
6. Is popular religion still a source of superstition and fear?
7. Are you comforted by Atomic immortality?
8. Is death "nothing to us," or was Epicurus trying to whistle past the graveyard?
9. What makes Epicurus a "sensible humanist"?
10. Is the doctrine of The Swerve really a "complete failure"? Do you think Epicurus thought it a proof of free will, a reason to resist determinism, an anticipation of modern physical theories of quantum indeterminacy, or... ?
11. Is human happiness inseparable from the life of the senses?
12. Is hell a psychological projection?
13. Was Berkeley crazy?
14. Are feelings a better guide to the good life than reason? Or are both equally important?
“...In addition to matters of style and approach, large differences between Stoicism and Epicureanism emerge in their almost entirely opposed views of nature. Although the Stoics agreed with the Epicureans that most people do not realize what sort of universe they are living in, and so are bound to end up confused in their attitudes to life, they thought that the Epicureans were just as ignorant as anyone else—if not more so. There was just one thing the Epicureans were right about: that everything was physical. In opposition to Plato and Aristotle, both the Epicureans and the Stoics were firm materialists. There were not two worlds, as Plato had said, consisting on the one hand of ordinary physical things and on the other of ideal Forms and souls. According to the Stoics, Plato’s ideal Forms were really just concepts in the mind, which is a physical thing, and so were themselves fundamentally physical. As for the soul, Plato was wrong to suggest that it consisted of some non-material stuff, and Aristotle was wrong to say that it was not made of any sort of stuff at all. For the Stoics and the Epicureans, it was made of the same material stuff as everything else. Still, on every other question about nature, the two Hellenistic schools were at loggerheads.
The Epicureans said that the world is the unplanned product of haphazard forces; the Stoics said it is rationally organized down to the last detail. The Epicureans said that the universe does not operate with any purposes in mind and that the gods are permanently on holiday; the Stoics retorted that a beneficent God, or providence, is thoroughly in charge and always on the job. The Epicureans said that the course of nature is not wholly determined in advance—there are, for instance, random swerves of atoms; the Stoics said that everything unfolds according to fate in an inexorable chain of cause and effect, and, moreover, that it will unfold in exactly the same way again and again in a cycle of cosmic creation and destruction. The Epicureans held that each person is completely free in his actions; the Stoics denied this, because of their belief in fate (though they still held that people are morally responsible for what they do). The Epicureans said that reality consists of atoms colliding by chance in the void to form everything we see; the Stoics said that matter is suffused with a sort of fiery breath (pneuma) that animates, organizes and directs it into various shapes and forms, and that atoms have nothing to do with it...”
— Dream of Reason: A History of Western Philosophy from the Greeks to the Renaissance by Anthony Gottlieb
Also see
Graceful-life philosophies
I mentioned in my posted introduction to students that I consider myself a kind of epicurean, and invited them to tell us on Opening Day (for extra credit) what that means. This might help.
"Where the Hellenistic philosophies excelled was the production of what could be called secular religions. They were based on self-help–oriented doctrines often borrowed from the earlier philosophers but interpreted and presented in a way that made more direct sense to a lot of people. I'm calling them graceful-life philosophies to distinguish them from other philosophy. Their goals were practical happiness, and they were not merely theoretical about it: they provided community, mediations, and events. In this they were more like religions, but they did not identify themselves as religions and they had remarkably little use for God or gods.
The Hellenistic graceful-life philosophies had a lot in common. The experience of doubt in a heterogeneous, cosmopolitan world is a bit like being lost in a forest, unendingly beckoned by a thousand possible routes. At every juncture, with every step, one is confronted with alternative paths, so that the second-guessing becomes more infuriating even than the fact of being lost. After a direction is chosen, one is constantly met with another tree in one's path. What do you do if you come from a culture that had a powerful sense of home and local value, and now you are lost in something vast and sprawling, meaningless and strange? The stronger your belief in that half-remembered home, the more likely you are to panic, to grow claustrophobic among the trees and beneath their skyless canopy. Hellenistic men and women felt a desperate desire to get out of the seemingly endless, friendless woods.
The graceful-life philosophies of this period were able to achieve an amazing rescue mission for the human being lost in the woods and bone-tired of searching for home. They did this by noticing that we could stop being lost if we were to just stop trying to get out of the forest. Instead, we could pick some blueberries, sit beneath a tree, and start describing how the sun-dappled forest floor shimmers in the breeze. The initial horror of being lost utterly disappears when you come to believe fully that there is no town out there, beyond the forest, to which you are headed. If there is no release, no going home, then this must be home, this shimmering instant replete with blueberries. Hang a sign that says HOME on a tree and you're done; just try to have a good time. Thus the cosmopolitan doubter looks back on earlier generations with bemused sympathy—they were mistaken—and looks upon believing contemporaries with real pity, as creatures scurrying through the forest, idiotically searching for a way out of the human condition. After all, it isn't so bad if you just settle in and accept a few difficult ideas from the get-go."
— Doubt: A History: The Great Doubters and Their Legacy of Innovation from Socrates and Jesus to Thomas Jefferson and Emily Dickinson by Jennifer Hecht
And see The Swerve: How the World Became Modern by Stephen Greenblatt...
Nice epicurean message here:
The day is short The night is long Why do we work so hard To get what we don’t even want? We work so hard to get ahead of the game Work half our lives until we’ve won. And then one day we sit on the edge of our bed And we think, “Lord, what have I done?” The day is short The night is long Why do we work so hard To get what you don’t even want? The man in the suit comes home and kisses his babies goodbye. “Daddy’s got to go on a trip, honey, oh no, don’t you cry.” He’s gone for a week then he’s home for a day. Well, pretty soon the babies won’t cry when Daddy’s gone away. The day is short The night is long Why do you work so hard To get what you don’t even want? You know we go to the mall and we go from store to store. Everybody seems to be wasting time until death walks through the door. And then you look at all your merchandise and you see We paid too high a price, you’ll see The day is short The night is long Why do we work so hard To get what you don’t even want
1. (1) How is the public image of Epicurus that has come down to us "gravely flawed"?
ReplyDeleteEpicurus’ image has been distorted over time; he is often misrepresented as an atheist, a hedonist, or merely a materialist, when in fact his philosophy was far more nuanced.
“The public image of Epicurus has come down to us gravely flawed. The educated layman has picked up various stereotypes to the effect that he was an epicure, an atheist, a pleasure-monger, and an ethical materialist. The introduction and commentary of this book attempt to correct these grievous and unnecessary errors…”
(Preface)
2. (9) What makes Epicurus a "sensible humanist"?
Epicurus is called a sensible humanist because he kept his focus on relieving human suffering and fear, instead of speculating endlessly about infinite worlds or abstract cosmology.
“The possibilities of propagating the true gospel of Epicureanism thus become tremendous, but Epicurus as a sensible humanist confines himself to the task of reducing human unhappiness locally and never raises such questions.”
(II. First Principles of Atomism and Their Implications)
3. (13) Was Berkeley crazy?
No — Berkeley was not crazy. His denial of matter was a logical extension of empiricism. He argued that since we only know our perceptions, “matter” is an unnecessary and misleading postulate.
“Bishop Berkeley, more consistently reduced all qualities to subjective status … ‘Matter,’ then, is a totally useless and misleading postulate, and any honest ‘common-sense’ empiricist can and must dispense with it!”
(IV. Sensation and Perception)
The questions you chose were the exact questions I was about to reply to until I read yours. I also agree with all of your answers, although it might be hard to disagree considering the answers are clearly stated in our text.
Delete**I somehow managed to post this as its own thing rather than the reply it was meant to be**
Another factor in the misrepresentation of Epicurus is the distortions of his philosophies by establishment religions. Religions were threatened by Epicurus's line of questioning and purposely or otherwise misrepresented his works. It was taught for a long time that his student, Lucretius, died of a broken heart (to discourage his philosophies that were anti-love.)
DeleteThe questions you chose were the exact questions I was about to reply to until I read yours. I also agree with all of your answers, although it might be hard to disagree considering the answers are clearly stated in our text.
ReplyDeleteIgnore this. This comment was meant to be a reply to the person above me.
Delete3. Do you agree with Heraclitus or Parmenides? Is it wise or appropriate to "philosophize in poetry"?
ReplyDeleteNo, I actually much prefer straightforward philosophizing, like Aristotle, in comparison to storytelling versions of philosophy, like Plato. Storytelling seems to be the choice for most of the greats.
I would not refer to it as inappropriate. Aristotle said that people were persuaded by logic, and I think that is true for a small percentage of the population, but by and far I think most people are persuaded by a good story that seemingly fits into their value system more than impressive logic.
7. Are you comforted by Atomic immortality?
ReplyDeleteNot really. Those parts of me that still exist after I die are no longer me.... but I am also not afraid of what comes after death. I imagine it to be exactly the same position I was in before birth. Non-existent and lacking the capacity to care.
Q6: Is popular religion still a source of superstition and fear?
ReplyDeleteA: I believe popular religion can still be a source of superstition and fear. I have heard a lot of pastors that use the fear of going to hell as a “motivation” for being a good Christian. Instead of spreading love, a lot of people spread fear.
Q: 12. Is hell a psychological projection?
ReplyDeleteA: This is a hard question to answer. I think this depends on your personal beliefs. I definitely struggle with the concept of heaven and hell and eternal life. I think a lot of times, it can be used as a way to cope with the death of a loved one by having the comfort that they are now living an eternal life with no pain.
Q 14: Are feelings a better guide to the good life than reason? Or are both equally important?
ReplyDeleteA: I believe this can depend on your personal beliefs and how you make decisions. I am personally someone who leads with my heart instead of my head. I don’t know that I could say one is “better” than the other. I know a lot of people that lead with their head instead of their heart, but sometimes their decisions could not feel as satisfying, even though it might have been the smarter decision in that moment. While I have sometimes gotten hurt by leading with my heart, I have always learned a valuable lesson and I don’t usually end up regretting the initial decision.
Q- 2. What question expresses the metaphysical problem of The One and the Many? Do you think the senses are more a veil from or a bridge to the real world?
ReplyDeleteA: "Is it possible to penetrate the veil of the senses, which reveal the world as multiple and diversified, and to discover some underlying unity from which the many may be derived?"
I think they are a bridge. Epicurus' view is a reductionist perspective. Logically, he is correct -- everything is made of atoms and the void they move within. However, he removes the human experience within that reduction. To me, reducing life as we know it to atoms and the void is not an answer to anything -- it is merely a breeding ground for nihilism because it removes the uniqueness of life itself.
4. I dont think empty space really exists. Even if something looks empty, science shows that there are still particles, energy and forces moving around in it. What seems like nothing is actually full of invisible activity. Even space itself is part of the universe. This means that it can't just be pure nothingness. It is always holding something, even if no one can see it, as scary as that sounds.
ReplyDelete7. I'm not really comforted by atomic immortality because even though my atoms might live on, that doesn't mean I do. My thoughts, memories, and personality won't continue just because my atoms get recycled. It's interesting to think about, but it doesn't take away the fact that my sense of self needs.
ReplyDelete